This is part of an ongoing series about preemptive war in
the Book of Mormon. See part
one, part
two, part two(a), part
three, part
four, part
five, part
six, part
seven, and now part eight.
We read in the second chapter of Helaman:
6 And it came to pass as [Kiskumen] went forth towards the
judgment-seat to destroy Helaman, behold one of the servants of Helaman, having
been out by night, and having obtained, through disguise, a knowledge of those
plans which had been laid by this band to destroy Helaman—
7 And it came to pass that he met Kishkumen, and he gave
unto him a sign; therefore Kishkumen made known unto him the object of his
desire, desiring that he would conduct him to the judgment-seat that he might
murder Helaman.
8 And when the servant of Helaman had known all the heart of
Kishkumen, and how that it was his object to murder, and also that it was the
object of all those who belonged to his band to murder, and to rob, and to gain
power, (and this was their secret plan, and their combination) the servant of
Helaman said unto Kishkumen: Let us go forth unto the judgment-seat.
9 Now this did please Kishkumen exceedingly, for he did
suppose that he should accomplish his design; but behold, the servant of
Helaman, as they were going forth unto the judgment-seat, did stab Kishkumen
even to the heart, that he fell dead without a groan.
When Helaman’s servant killed Kishkumen this seemed like a
divinely ordained protection of Helaman(2).
Kishkumen’s guilt is established by the narration in verse 8. Curiously, the
Book of Mormon says that Nephite law didn’t punish a person’s belief Alma
30:7,9; a person was only punished after committing murder or robbery
(Alma 30:10). Kishkumen did murder the preceding chief judge (Helaman 1:9) but
hadn’t yet committed this crime. Yet there is no record of the servant’s
punishment over his preemptive murder or taking justice into his own hands over
Kishkumen’s previous murder, and no editorial critique from Mormon, except a
warning that the Gadianton Robbers would overthrow the people of Nephi (Helaman
2:13-14). The text simply shows that Helaman was a prophet and good leader
whose servant righteously defended him.
Various thoughtful theorists from hundreds of years in the
past have explained why that can remain a just action. Except none of that
thought has been applied to LDS scripture. Patrick Mason summarizes many Latter
Day Saints when he calls just war theory “neither broad nor comprehensive
enough.”
Even National Security professionals feel the need to defend the use of just
war for members of Christ’s church to resolve modern problems.
But there is rich material that applies. The theorist,
Samuel Pufendorf, writing around the time of the 30 Years War compared the
right of preemptive or even preventive action to a person that sees a “charging
assailant with sword in hand.”
The modern theorist Michael Walzer suggests that someone being hunted has a
right to ambush his attacker.
In both instances the basic premise is than an individual who sees an attack in
progress doesn’t have to wait for the first blow to defend themselves.
The early modern theorist Hugo Grotius explained those
underlying principles when he wrote that if the state faced a danger that was
facing “immediate and certain” danger or an attack that “commenced but not
carried through” the state could take preemptive action. Commenced but not
carried through might sound odd, but you’ve already read several examples like
that in this post. It would be like the individual has drawn the sword, sworn
an oath to kill you, but has only raised and not swung the sword yet. Or maybe
it would be like a would-be assassin that has sworn an oath to kill the chief judge
and has arrived on the scene with a dagger to do the deed, and that assassin
killed a previous judge (Helaman2:3). A modern example would be that a nation
has launched its bombers in a nuclear strike, but they haven’t hit their target
yet. Even though President Eisenhower is often quoted as an opponent of
preemptive war, he
admitted during the Berlin crisis that if placed in that situation he would
launch a preemptive nuclear first strike.
The modern conception of just preemptive war is referred to
as the Caroline standard. In stopping an arms shipment to Canadian separatists
the US navy took preemptive action to destroy the Caroline. Daniel Webster
argued that the “instant and overwhelming need for self-defense, leaving no
choice and no moment for deliberation” justified the attack.
In short, the main criteria summarized from theorists as far
back as the 16th century suggests that preemptive warfare is
justified when a threat must have intent, means, and imminence.
Applied to the case of Helaman’s servant, the servant knew they had intent. A
previous chief judge had been killed, and the servant attended the meeting of
conspirators planning the murder of Helaman. Kishkumen had the weapon we would
use to perform the killing and thought he had been granted access to the chief
judge. An assassination would happen within moments. This seems to meet all of
the requirements but there are still questions about the theory itself and its
modern application.
The major problem with this standard is the rather subjective
nature of “imminent.” Grotius for example, used the example of a plot formed by
robbers to argue for a more restrained and patient approached led by law
enforcement approach instead of a preemptive strike. He wrote, if they “formed
a plot, prepar[ed] an ambuscade, poisoning, or readied a false accusation [the
planner] cannot lawfully be killed either if danger can in any other way be
avoided, or if [the ruler] thought delays could afford remedies.”
Justified self-defense within the criminal law is founded
upon the principle of defending yourself against an immediate attack. Not a
preemptive attack because the two parties have been threatening each other, or
a long-awaited revenge killing in retaliation. Going back to Webster and the
Caroline case again, the preemptive attack must be in the moment when the
threat of deadly force creates and “overwhelming need” for force and the attack
must be made when there is “no moment for deliberation.”
But other theorists took a rather expansive view. A
contemporary theorist of Grotius named Alberico Gentili argued that “at the
first signs trouble are perceived, it is easy to find a solution, but if one
lets trouble develop medicine will be too late.”
This is the exact same argument that the classical Chinese theorist Shizi
made. Even a tree so big that it shields the sky was, at its beginning,
only as thick as the base of a tree sprout: easy to get rid of. But once it has
fully manifested itself, a hundred people using hatchets and axes are unable to
fell it!
The enlightenment writer Emil Vattel wrote that a state can
attack “as soon as [its neighbors] has been given evidence of injustice, greed,
pride, ambition, or desire of dominating over its neighbors.”
The problem with the reasoning of the above theorists is
that just about any change or perceived change can justify those conditions,
and anything can be spun by a ruler seeking expansive war to justify those
requirements.
In short, there is significant debate over how immediate
something must be and how important that qualification is with answers ranging from
very to none. To better understand the differences we might return to the
preemptive attack from Helaman’s servant. At first glance it seems like
Helaman’s servant was justified, but he many not have been. The text says that
he received this information the night before. Thus, the servant of Helaman didn’t
have to resort to killing. He could have notified Helaman so the latter wasn’t
on the judgement seat when Kishkumen came. The servant could have called for
additional guards to arrest Kishkumen when the latter arrived on the scene. The
key point is that unlike the Webster’s reasoning in the Caroline case, the
servant had time to deliberate. But the servant resorted to killing, when he
had been out by night (Helaman 2:6) and had thus had time to arrange a non-lethal
way to end the approaching attack.
But the problem of judging immediacy is even tougher in the
modern era. For example, if the US waited until the 9/11 attacks were
“commenced but not carried out” as Grotius said, “left no moment for
deliberation” from the Caroline case, or were clearly imminent as the standard
demands, then the planes would have already been on their way to the twin
towers. America would have been forced to kill several hundred innocent passengers
to stop the terrorist attacks.
The answer to the problem of immediacy then, is to examine
the danger and its magnitude combined with the other two criteria, intent and
means. Terrorists have been attacking America for years, so like the Gadianton
Robbers, they have shown intent. But unlike Kishkumen’s dagger, terrorists
armed with nuclear weapons have much stronger means. With a nuclear weapon they
could kill millions in a single attack. Sounding very similar to my writings:
John F. Kennedy wrote said, “We no longer live in a world where only the actual
firing of weapons represents a sufficient challenge to a nations security to
constitute maximum peril. Nuclear weapons are so destructive and ballistic
missiles are so swift, that any substantially increased possibility of their
use or any sudden change in deployment may well be regarded as a threat to
peace.
Or as I wrote using my good instincts about the dangers of
nuclear weapons:
During
the Cold War the United States could nominally count on the international order
to restrain the actions of the enemy.[14] Now, the United States faces regimes that explicitly reject that world order…But
unlike ancient times, strategic surprise in the modern age may not simply
represent the destruction of a small ancient city, but could take the form of a
nuclear attack in a highly populated metropolis. The power of nuclear weapons
increases the ability of an opponent to end the war at a stroke.[15]
Thus, if a terrorist group fulfilled the first two criteria,
means and intent, but the timing of the attack remained unclear, it would be
incredibly dangerous to wait and accept a single blow (let alone three,) or
wait until the attack was commenced but not carried out. Instead, as a
justified self-defense America would launch a preemptive and even preventive
strike.
Many Latter-Day Saints wrongly presume that scriptures like
section 98 are a strict guide to foreign policy and argue the neighbor should
receive three attacks. (As Duane Boyce pointed out,
even that is confusing. Do you count three bullets, three magazines, or three
battles?) But a person has a basic right to life, and a right to defend it. Reason,
natural law as theorists would say, or some common sense regarding nuclear
weapons suggests waiting to receive even a single attack is foolish and
even wicked because it will be fatal.
That doesn’t mean a person or nation should go to the
extreme and launch an attack at the mere hint of attack. (Though there are some
theorists that go that far.) Instead,
there are many options in between a destructive strike at the first provocation
and waiting to receive the likely fatal first blow. A besieged neighbor might intercept
the weapons shipments, which means the neighboring enemy would have far less
ability, or means, to attack you at all. (Think of the Cuban Missile Crisis.
Having nuclear weapons 90 miles from America was a grave threat and justified a
military response to remove them, but part of the concern of the Kennedy
administration was a proportional response, hence the blockade.) Though the
principle is clear, modern crises aren’t quit as simple.
Thus, Americans should be aware of terrorist ideology
(intent.) They must continue to take steps to prevent them from obtaining means
like weapons, and especially any WMDs. But they don’t have to for imminent
attacks before striking, as that would often be too late. Instead, to protect
lives they should launch devastating strikes against terrorists before the
threats materialize.
Helaman chapter two is not simply a short cloak and dagger tale, or introduction to the Gadianton Robbers that eventually dominate the text. But become an important case study about the just and righteous principles behind first strikes. If an enemy shows intent, means, and imminency (however sometimes vague the last might be), like Helaman’s servant, they have a right to strike first with preemptive and even preventive war. They might thoughtfully consider other options less of force, but the right remains and often there is no time for those other options.
I work as a free lance author. If you found value in this work please consider donating using the paypal button below, or buy one of my books linked in the top left.